08-401/The Fundamental Theorem: Difference between revisions

From Drorbn
Jump to navigationJump to search
No edit summary
 
No edit summary
Line 1: Line 1:
{{08-401/Navigation}}
{{08-401/Navigation}}
{{In Preparation}}


The statement appearing here, which is a weak version of the full '''fundamental theorem of Galois theory''', is taken from Gallian's book and is meant to match our discussion in class. The proof is taken from Hungerford's book, except modified to fit our notations and conventions and simplified as per our weakened requirements.
==The Fundamental Theorem of Galois Theory==

The statement appearing here, which is a weak version of the full theorem, is taken from Gallian's book and is meant to match our discussion in class. The proof is taken from Hungerford's book, except modified to fit our notations and conventions and simplified as per our weakened requirements.


Here and everywhere below our base field <math>F</math> will be a field of characteristic 0.
Here and everywhere below our base field <math>F</math> will be a field of characteristic 0.


===Statement===
==Statement==


'''Theorem.''' Let <math>E</math> be a splitting field over <math>F</math>. Then there is a bijective correspondence between the set <math>\{K:E/K/F\}</math> of intermediate field extensions <math>K</math> lying between <math>F</math> and <math>E</math> and the set <math>\{H:H<\operatorname{Gal}(E/F)\}</math> of subgroups <math>H</math> of the Galois group <math>\operatorname{Gal}(E/F)</math> of the original extension <math>E/F</math>:
'''Theorem.''' Let <math>E</math> be a splitting field over <math>F</math>. Then there is a bijective correspondence between the set <math>\{K:E/K/F\}</math> of intermediate field extensions <math>K</math> lying between <math>F</math> and <math>E</math> and the set <math>\{H:H<\operatorname{Gal}(E/F)\}</math> of subgroups <math>H</math> of the Galois group <math>\operatorname{Gal}(E/F)</math> of the original extension <math>E/F</math>:
Line 20: Line 19:
# Splitting fields correspond to normal subgroups: If <math>K</math> in <math>E/K/F</math> is the splitting field of a polynomial in <math>F[x]</math> then <math>\operatorname{Gal}(E/K)</math> is normal in <math>\operatorname{Gal}(E/F)</math> and <math>\operatorname{Gal}(K/F)\cong\operatorname{Gal}(E/F)/\operatorname{Gal}(E/K)</math>.
# Splitting fields correspond to normal subgroups: If <math>K</math> in <math>E/K/F</math> is the splitting field of a polynomial in <math>F[x]</math> then <math>\operatorname{Gal}(E/K)</math> is normal in <math>\operatorname{Gal}(E/F)</math> and <math>\operatorname{Gal}(K/F)\cong\operatorname{Gal}(E/F)/\operatorname{Gal}(E/K)</math>.


===Lemmas===
==Lemmas==


The two lemmas below belong to earlier chapters but we skipped them in class.
The two lemmas below belong to earlier chapters but we skipped them in class.


====The Primitive Element Theorem====
===The Primitive Element Theorem===


The celebrated "Primitive Element Theorem" is just a lemma for us:
The celebrated "Primitive Element Theorem" is just a lemma for us:
Line 32: Line 31:
'''Proof.''' See the proof of Theorem 21.6 on page 375 of Gallian's book. <math>\Box</math>
'''Proof.''' See the proof of Theorem 21.6 on page 375 of Gallian's book. <math>\Box</math>


====Splitting Fields are Good at Splitting====
===Splitting Fields are Good at Splitting===


'''Lemma 2.''' (Compare with Hungerford's Theorem 10.15 on page 355). If <math>E</math> is a splitting field of some polynomial <math>f</math> over <math>F</math> and some irreducible polynomial <math>p\in F[x]</math> has a root <math>v</math> in <math>E</math>, then <math>p</math> splits in <math>E</math>.
'''Lemma 2.''' (Compare with Hungerford's Theorem 10.15 on page 355). If <math>E</math> is a splitting field of some polynomial <math>f</math> over <math>F</math> and some irreducible polynomial <math>p\in F[x]</math> has a root <math>v</math> in <math>E</math>, then <math>p</math> splits in <math>E</math>.
Line 46: Line 45:
and <math>E(z)</math> is obtained by adding all the roots of <math>f</math> to <math>F(z)</math>. <math>\Box</math>
and <math>E(z)</math> is obtained by adding all the roots of <math>f</math> to <math>F(z)</math>. <math>\Box</math>


===Proof of The Fundamental Theorem===
==Proof of The Fundamental Theorem==


====The Bijection====
===The Bijection===
'''Proof of <math>\Psi\circ\Phi=I</math>.''' More precisely, we need to show that if <math>K</math> is an intermediate field between <math>E</math> and <math>F</math>, then <math>E_{\operatorname{Gal}(E/K)}=K</math>. The inclusion <math>E_{\operatorname{Gal}(E/K)}\supset K</math> is easy, so we turn to prove the other inclusion. Let <math>v\in E-K</math> be an element of <math>E</math> which is not in <math>K</math>. We need to show that there is some automorphism <math>\phi\in\operatorname{Gal}(E/K)</math> for which <math>\phi(v)\neq v</math>; if such a <math>\phi</math> exists it follows that <math>v\not\in E_{\operatorname{Gal}(E/K)}</math> and this implies the other inclusion. So let <math>p</math> be the minimal polynomial of <math>v</math> over <math>K</math>. It is not of degree 1; if it was, we'd have that <math>v\in K</math> contradicting the choice of <math>v</math>. By lemma 2 and using the fact that <math>E</math> is a splitting extension, we know that <math>p</math> splits in <math>E</math>, so <math>E</math> contains all the roots of <math>p</math>. Over a field of characteristic 0 irreducible polynomials cannot have multiple roots and hence <math>p</math> must have at least one other root; call it <math>w</math>. Since <math>v</math> and <math>w</math> have the same minimal polynomial over <math>K</math>, we know that <math>K(v)</math> and <math>K(w)</math> are isomorphic; furthermore, there is an isomorphism <math>\phi_0:K(v)\to K(w)</math> so that <math>\phi_0|_K=I</math> yet <math>\phi_0(v)=w</math>. But <math>E</math> is a splitting field of some polynomial <math>f</math> over <math>F</math> and hence also over <math>K(v)</math> and over <math>K(w)</math>. By the uniqueness of splitting fields, the isomorphism <math>\phi_0</math> can be extended to an isomorphism <math>\phi:E\to E</math>; i.e., to an automorphism of <math>E</math>. but then <math>\phi|_K=\phi_0|_K=I</math> so <math>\phi\in\operatorname{Gal}(E/K)</math>, yet <math>\phi(v)=w\neq v</math>, as required. <math>\Box</math>
'''Proof of <math>\Psi\circ\Phi=I</math>.''' More precisely, we need to show that if <math>K</math> is an intermediate field between <math>E</math> and <math>F</math>, then <math>E_{\operatorname{Gal}(E/K)}=K</math>. The inclusion <math>E_{\operatorname{Gal}(E/K)}\supset K</math> is easy, so we turn to prove the other inclusion. Let <math>v\in E-K</math> be an element of <math>E</math> which is not in <math>K</math>. We need to show that there is some automorphism <math>\phi\in\operatorname{Gal}(E/K)</math> for which <math>\phi(v)\neq v</math>; if such a <math>\phi</math> exists it follows that <math>v\not\in E_{\operatorname{Gal}(E/K)}</math> and this implies the other inclusion. So let <math>p</math> be the minimal polynomial of <math>v</math> over <math>K</math>. It is not of degree 1; if it was, we'd have that <math>v\in K</math> contradicting the choice of <math>v</math>. By lemma 2 and using the fact that <math>E</math> is a splitting extension, we know that <math>p</math> splits in <math>E</math>, so <math>E</math> contains all the roots of <math>p</math>. Over a field of characteristic 0 irreducible polynomials cannot have multiple roots and hence <math>p</math> must have at least one other root; call it <math>w</math>. Since <math>v</math> and <math>w</math> have the same minimal polynomial over <math>K</math>, we know that <math>K(v)</math> and <math>K(w)</math> are isomorphic; furthermore, there is an isomorphism <math>\phi_0:K(v)\to K(w)</math> so that <math>\phi_0|_K=I</math> yet <math>\phi_0(v)=w</math>. But <math>E</math> is a splitting field of some polynomial <math>f</math> over <math>F</math> and hence also over <math>K(v)</math> and over <math>K(w)</math>. By the uniqueness of splitting fields, the isomorphism <math>\phi_0</math> can be extended to an isomorphism <math>\phi:E\to E</math>; i.e., to an automorphism of <math>E</math>. but then <math>\phi|_K=\phi_0|_K=I</math> so <math>\phi\in\operatorname{Gal}(E/K)</math>, yet <math>\phi(v)=w\neq v</math>, as required. <math>\Box</math>


Line 65: Line 64:
and hence <math>f\in E_H[x]</math>. Clearly <math>f(u)=0</math>, so <math>p|f</math>, so <math>[E:E_H]=\deg p\leq \deg f=n=|H|</math>, proving the third inequality above. <math>\Box</math>
and hence <math>f\in E_H[x]</math>. Clearly <math>f(u)=0</math>, so <math>p|f</math>, so <math>[E:E_H]=\deg p\leq \deg f=n=|H|</math>, proving the third inequality above. <math>\Box</math>


====The Properties====
===The Properties===


'''Property 1.''' If <math>H_1\subset H_2</math> then <math>E_{H_1}\supset E_{H_2}</math> and if <math>K_1\subset K_2</math> then <math>\operatorname{Gal}(E/K_1)>\operatorname{Gal}(E/K_1)</math>.
'''Property 1.''' If <math>H_1\subset H_2</math> then <math>E_{H_1}\supset E_{H_2}</math> and if <math>K_1\subset K_2</math> then <math>\operatorname{Gal}(E/K_1)>\operatorname{Gal}(E/K_1)</math>.

Revision as of 08:26, 30 March 2008

Announcements go here
In Preparation

The information below is preliminary and cannot be trusted! (v)

The statement appearing here, which is a weak version of the full fundamental theorem of Galois theory, is taken from Gallian's book and is meant to match our discussion in class. The proof is taken from Hungerford's book, except modified to fit our notations and conventions and simplified as per our weakened requirements.

Here and everywhere below our base field will be a field of characteristic 0.

Statement

Theorem. Let be a splitting field over . Then there is a bijective correspondence between the set of intermediate field extensions lying between and and the set of subgroups of the Galois group of the original extension :

.

The bijection is given by mapping every intermediate extension to the subgroup of elements in that preserve ,

,

and reversely, by mapping every subgroup of to its fixed field :

.

This correspondence has the following further properties:

  1. It is inclusion-reversing: if then and if then .
  2. It is degree/index respecting: and .
  3. Splitting fields correspond to normal subgroups: If in is the splitting field of a polynomial in then is normal in and .

Lemmas

The two lemmas below belong to earlier chapters but we skipped them in class.

The Primitive Element Theorem

The celebrated "Primitive Element Theorem" is just a lemma for us:

Lemma 1. Let and be algebraic elements of some extension of . Then there exists a single element of so that . (And so by induction, every finite extension of is "simple", meaning, is generated by a single element, called "a primitive element" for that extension).

Proof. See the proof of Theorem 21.6 on page 375 of Gallian's book.

Splitting Fields are Good at Splitting

Lemma 2. (Compare with Hungerford's Theorem 10.15 on page 355). If is a splitting field of some polynomial over and some irreducible polynomial has a root in , then splits in .

Proof. Let be a splitting field of over . We need to show that if is a root of in , then (so all the roots of are in and hence splits in ). Consider the two extensions

and .

The "smaller fields" and in these two extensions are isomorphic as they both arise by adding a root of the same irreducible polynomial () to the base field . The "larger fields" and in these two extensions are both the splitting fields of the same polynomial () over the respective "small fields", as is a splitting extension for and we can use the sub-lemma below. Thus by the uniqueness of splitting extensions, the isomorphism between and extends to an isomorphism between and , and in particular these two fields are isomorphic and so . Since all the degrees involved are finite it follows from the last equality and from that and therefore . Therefore .

Sub-lemma. If is a splitting extension of some polynomial and is an element of some larger extension of , then is also a splitting extension of .

Proof. Let be all the roots of in . Then they remain roots of in , and since completely splits already in , these are all the roots of in . So

,

and is obtained by adding all the roots of to .

Proof of The Fundamental Theorem

The Bijection

Proof of . More precisely, we need to show that if is an intermediate field between and , then . The inclusion is easy, so we turn to prove the other inclusion. Let be an element of which is not in . We need to show that there is some automorphism for which ; if such a exists it follows that and this implies the other inclusion. So let be the minimal polynomial of over . It is not of degree 1; if it was, we'd have that contradicting the choice of . By lemma 2 and using the fact that is a splitting extension, we know that splits in , so contains all the roots of . Over a field of characteristic 0 irreducible polynomials cannot have multiple roots and hence must have at least one other root; call it . Since and have the same minimal polynomial over , we know that and are isomorphic; furthermore, there is an isomorphism so that yet . But is a splitting field of some polynomial over and hence also over and over . By the uniqueness of splitting fields, the isomorphism can be extended to an isomorphism ; i.e., to an automorphism of . but then so , yet , as required.

Proof of . More precisely we need to show that if is a subgroup of the Galois group of over , then . The inclusion is easy. Note that is finite since we've proven previously that Galois groups of finite extensions are finite and hence is finite. We will prove the following sequence of inequalities:

This sequence and the finiteness of imply that these quantities are all equal and since it follows that as required.

The first inequality above follows immediately from the inclusion .

By the Primitive Element Theorem (Lemma 1) we know that there is some element so that . Let be the minimal polynomial of over . Distinct elements of map to distinct roots of , but has exactly roots. Hence , proving the second inequality above.

Let be an enumeration of all the elements of , let (with as above), and let be the polynomial

.

Clearly, . Furthermore, if , then left multiplication by permutes the 's (this is always true in groups), and hence the sequence is a permutation of the sequence , hence

,

and hence . Clearly , so , so , proving the third inequality above.

The Properties

Property 1. If then and if then .

Proof of Property 1. Easy.

Property 2. and .

Proof of Property 2. If , then as was shown within the proof of . But every is for some , so for every between and . The second equality follows from the first and from the multiplicativity of the degree/order/index in towers of extensions and in towers of groups:

Property 3. If in is the splitting field of a polynomial in then is normal in and .

Proof of Property 3. We will define a surjective (onto) group homomorphism whose kernel is . This shows that is normal in (kernels of homomorphisms are always normal) and then by the first isomorphism theorem for groups, we'll have that .

Let be in and let be an element of . Let be the minimal polynomial of in . Since is a splitting field, lemma 2 implies that splits in , and hence all the other roots of are also in . As is a root of , it follows that and hence . But since is an isomorphism, and hence . Hence the restriction of to is an automorphism of , so we can define .

Clearly, is a group homomorphism. The kernel of is those automorphisms of whose restriction to is the identity. That is, it is . Finally, as is a splitting extension, so is . So every automorphism of extends to an automorphism of by the uniqueness statement for splitting extensions. But this means that is onto.