11-1100-Pgadey-Lect5: Difference between revisions
No edit summary |
No edit summary |
||
(8 intermediate revisions by the same user not shown) | |||
Line 1: | Line 1: | ||
== Simplicity of <math>A_n</math>. == |
|||
;Claim |
;Claim |
||
: <math>A_n |
: <math>A_n</math> is simple for <math>n \neq 4</math>. |
||
For <math>n = 1 </math> we have that <math>A_n = \{e\} </math> which is simple. |
For <math>n = 1 </math> we have that <math>A_n = \{e\} </math> which is simple. |
||
For <math>n=2 </math> we have that <math>S_n = \{(12), e\} </math>, and once again <math>A_n = \{e\} </math>. |
For <math>n=2 </math> we have that <math>S_n = \{(12), e\} </math>, and once again <math>A_n = \{e\} </math>. |
||
For <math>n = 3 </math> we have that <math>A_n = \{e, (123), (132)\} \simeq Z/3Z </math> which is of prime order, and hence has no proper subgroups (by Lagrange). It follows that it has no normal proper subgroups. |
For <math>n = 3 </math> we have that <math>A_n = \{e, (123), (132)\} \simeq Z/3Z </math> which is of prime order, and hence has no proper subgroups (by Lagrange). It follows that it has no normal proper subgroups. |
||
For <math>n = 4 </math> we have |
For <math>n = 4 </math> we have <span style="color:red">Dror's Favourite Homomorphism (the map <math>S_4 \rightarrow S_3</math> given by a coloured tetrahedron [http://katlas.math.toronto.edu/drorbn/AcademicPensieve/Classes/11-1100/ColouredTetrahedron.png (link)] </span> |
||
⚫ | |||
⚫ | |||
⚫ | |||
Some computations: |
|||
⚫ | |||
These are the main ingredients of the proof |
|||
⚫ | |||
⚫ | |||
These are the main ingredients of the proof. The first equality says that a product of transpositions of non-disjoint pairs is a 3-cycle, the second equality says that the product of a pair of disjoint transpositions is a product of three cycles. Thus any product of two transpositions can be written a product of three cycles. <span style="color:green">[ The second equality is amusing with physical objects. ]</span> |
|||
; Lemma 1 |
; Lemma 1 |
||
: <math>A_n |
: <math>A_n</math> is generated by three cycles in <math>S_n</math>. That is, <math>A_n = \langle \{ (ijk) \in S_n \} \rangle</math>. |
||
We have that each element of <math>A_n </math> is the product of an even number of transpositions |
We have that each element of <math>A_n </math> is the product of an even number of transpositions <span style="color:green">(braid diagrams, computation with polynomials, etc)</span>. But we can replace a pair of 2-cycles with one or two 3-cycles by the computation above. It follows that any element of the alternating group can be rewritten as a product of 3-cycles. |
||
; Lemma 2 |
; Lemma 2 |
||
: If <math>N \triangleleft A_n |
: If <math>N \triangleleft A_n</math> contains a 3-cycle then <math>N=A_n</math>. |
||
Up to changing notation, we have that <math>(123) \in N |
Up to changing notation, we have that <math>(123) \in N</math>. We show that <math>(123)^\sigma \in N</math> for any <math>\sigma \in S_n</math>. By normality, we have this for <math>\sigma \in A_n</math>. If <math>\sigma \not\in A_n</math> we can write <math>\sigma = (12)\sigma'</math> for <math>\sigma \in A_n</math>. But then <math>(123)^{(12)} = (123)^2</math> and thus |
||
< |
<math> (123)^\sigma = \left( (123)^{(12)} \right)^{\sigma'} \in N</math> |
||
Since all 3-cycles are conjugate to <math>(123) |
Since all 3-cycles are conjugate to <math>(123)</math> we have that all 3-cycles are in <math>N</math>. It follows by Lemma 1 that <math>N = A_n</math>. |
||
; |
;''Case I'' |
||
: <math>N |
: <math>N</math> contains a cycle of length <math>\geq 4</math>. |
||
< |
<math> \sigma= (123456)\sigma' \in N \Rightarrow \sigma^{-1} (123) \sigma (123)^{-1} = (136) \in N </math> |
||
The claim then follows by Lemma 2. |
The claim then follows by Lemma 2. |
||
; |
;''Case II'' |
||
: If <math>N </math> contains an with two cycles of length 3. |
: If <math>N </math> contains an with two cycles of length 3. |
||
< |
<math> \sigma = (123)(456) \sigma' \in N \Rightarrow \sigma^{-1}(124)\sigma(124)^{-1} = (14263) \in N </math> |
||
The claim then follows by |
The claim then follows by ''Case I''. |
||
; |
;''Case III'' |
||
: If <math>N </math> contains <math>\sigma = (123)(\textrm{a product of disjoint 2-cycles}) </math> |
: If <math>N </math> contains <math>\sigma = (123)(\textrm{a product of disjoint 2-cycles}) </math> |
||
We have that <math>\sigma^2 = (132) \in N </math>. The claim then follows by Lemma 1. |
We have that <math>\sigma^2 = (132) \in N </math>. The claim then follows by Lemma 1. |
||
; |
;''Case IV'' |
||
: If every element of <math>N </math> is a product of disjoint 2-cycles. |
: If every element of <math>N </math> is a product of disjoint 2-cycles. |
||
We have that |
We have that |
||
< |
<math> \sigma = (12)(34)\sigma' \Rightarrow \sigma^{-1}(123)\sigma(123)^{-1} = (13)(24) = \tau \in N </math> |
||
But then <math>\tau^{-1}(125)\tau(125)^{-1} = (13452) \in N </math>. |
But then <math>\tau^{-1}(125)\tau(125)^{-1} = (13452) \in N </math>. |
||
The claim then follows by Case 1. |
The claim then follows by Case 1. |
||
<span style="color:green">[Note: This last case is the '''only''' place where we really use this mystical fifth element. Without it, this last step wouldn't go through.]</span> |
|||
== Throwback to <math>S_4</math> == |
|||
;Claim |
|||
:<math>S_4 </math> contains no normal <math>H </math> such that <math>H \simeq S_3 </math>. |
|||
< |
<math>S_3 </math> has an element of order three, therefore <math>H </math> does. We then conjugate to get all the three cycles. Then <math>H </math> is too big. |
||
[ Suppose that <math>(123) \in H </math>, then |
|||
< |
<math> S = \{ e, (123), (132), (124), (142), (134), (143), (234), (243)\} \subset H </math> |
||
Which implies that <math>|S_3| = 6 < 9 \leq |H| </math>, but since <math>H \simeq S_3 </math> we have <math>|H| = |S_3| </math>, a contradiction.] |
Which implies that <math>|S_3| = 6 < 9 \leq |H| </math>, but since <math>H \simeq S_3 </math> we have <math>|H| = |S_3| </math>, a contradiction.] |
||
== Group Actions == |
|||
; A group <math>G </math> acting on a set <math>X </math> |
; A group <math>G </math> acting on a set <math>X </math> |
||
Line 67: | Line 67: | ||
* [The above implies <math>ex = x </math> and <math>gy = x \Rightarrow g^{-1}y=x </math>.] |
* [The above implies <math>ex = x </math> and <math>gy = x \Rightarrow g^{-1}y=x </math>.] |
||
=== Examples of group actions === |
|||
* <math>G </math> acting on itself by conjugation (a right action). <math>(g,g') \mapsto g^{g'} </math> |
* <math>G </math> acting on itself by conjugation (a right action). <math>(g,g') \mapsto g^{g'} </math> |
||
* Let <math>S(X) </math> be the set of bijections from <math>X </math> to <math>X </math>, with group structure given by composition. We then have an <math>S(X) </math>-action of <math>X </math> given <math>x \mapsto gx : X \rightarrow X \in S(X) </math> |
* Let <math>S(X) </math> be the set of bijections from <math>X </math> to <math>X </math>, with group structure given by composition. We then have an <math>S(X) </math>-action of <math>X </math> given <math>x \mapsto gx : X \rightarrow X \in S(X) </math> |
||
<span style="color:green">["Where does the shirt come into the business?!" Dror's remark after talking about the symmetry of a student's shirt.]</span> |
|||
* If <math>G = (\mathcal{G}, \cdot) </math> is a group where <math>\mathcal{S} </math> is the underlying set of <math>G </math> and <math>\cdot </math> is the group multiplication. We have an action: <math>(g,s) = g \cdot s </math> this gives a map <math>G \rightarrow S(\mathcal{G}) </math>. |
* If <math>G = (\mathcal{G}, \cdot) </math> is a group where <math>\mathcal{S} </math> is the underlying set of <math>G </math> and <math>\cdot </math> is the group multiplication. We have an action: <math>(g,s) = g \cdot s </math> this gives a map <math>G \rightarrow S(\mathcal{G}) </math>. |
||
* <math>SO(n) </math> is the group of orientation preserving symmetries of the <math>(n-1) </math>-dimensional sphere. We have that <math>SO(2) \leq SO(3) </math> as the subgroup of rotations that fix the north and south pole. There is a map <math>SO(3)/SO(2) \rightarrow S^2 </math> given by looking at the image of the north pole. |
* <math>SO(n) </math> is the group of orientation preserving symmetries of the <math>(n-1) </math>-dimensional sphere. We have that <math>SO(2) \leq SO(3) </math> as the subgroup of rotations that fix the north and south pole. There is a map <math>SO(3)/SO(2) \rightarrow S^2 </math> given by looking at the image of the north pole. |
||
Line 78: | Line 78: | ||
: Show that <math>S_n </math> acting on <math>\{1, 2, \dots, n\} </math> and <math>S_n / S_{n-1} </math> are isomorphic <math>S_n </math>-sets. |
: Show that <math>S_n </math> acting on <math>\{1, 2, \dots, n\} </math> and <math>S_n / S_{n-1} </math> are isomorphic <math>S_n </math>-sets. |
||
<span style="color:green">[Dror violently resists rigorously defining a category. Gives a little speech about "things" and "arrows". Gives an example of taking a topological space <math>T </math> and then looking at the space of paths with identities given by staying still, and composition of paths given by concatenation.]</span> |
|||
; Claim |
; Claim |
||
: Left <math>G </math>-sets form a category. |
: Left <math>G </math>-sets form a category. |
||
@@color:green ; //[Dror: I'm being a little bit biased. I prefer the left over the right. Parker: Propaganda? ]//@@ |
|||
The objects of the category are actions <math>G \times X \rightarrow X </math>. The morphisms, if we have <math>X </math> and <math>Y </math> are <math>G </math>-sets, a morphism of <math>G </math>-sets is a function <math>\gamma : X \rightarrow Y </math> such that <math>\gamma(gx) = g(\gamma(x)) </math>. |
The objects of the category are actions <math>G \times X \rightarrow X </math>. The morphisms, if we have <math>X </math> and <math>Y </math> are <math>G </math>-sets, a morphism of <math>G </math>-sets is a function <math>\gamma : X \rightarrow Y </math> such that <math>\gamma(gx) = g(\gamma(x)) </math>. |
||
Line 94: | Line 92: | ||
the next statement combines the silly observation above, with the construction of an action of <math>G </math> on <math>G/H </math>. |
the next statement combines the silly observation above, with the construction of an action of <math>G </math> on <math>G/H </math>. |
||
; |
|||
;Claim |
|||
: Any <math>G </math>-set <math>X </math> is a disjoint unions of the |
: Any <math>G </math>-set <math>X </math> is a disjoint unions of the "transitive <math>G </math>-sets". And If <math>Y </math> is a transitive <math>G </math>-set, then <math>Y \simeq G/H </math> for some <math>H \leq G </math>. |
Latest revision as of 20:14, 4 October 2011
Simplicity of .
- Claim
- is simple for .
For we have that which is simple. For we have that , and once again . For we have that which is of prime order, and hence has no proper subgroups (by Lagrange). It follows that it has no normal proper subgroups.
For we have Dror's Favourite Homomorphism (the map given by a coloured tetrahedron (link)
[This proof is not a deep conceptual proof. It is the product of a lot of playing around with cycles, and generators. This is much like a solution to the Rubik's cube, it naturally arises from a lot of playing around -- but is not conceptually deep at all.]
We proceed with some unmotivated computations: These are the main ingredients of the proof. The first equality says that a product of transpositions of non-disjoint pairs is a 3-cycle, the second equality says that the product of a pair of disjoint transpositions is a product of three cycles. Thus any product of two transpositions can be written a product of three cycles. [ The second equality is amusing with physical objects. ]
- Lemma 1
- is generated by three cycles in . That is, .
We have that each element of is the product of an even number of transpositions (braid diagrams, computation with polynomials, etc). But we can replace a pair of 2-cycles with one or two 3-cycles by the computation above. It follows that any element of the alternating group can be rewritten as a product of 3-cycles.
- Lemma 2
- If contains a 3-cycle then .
Up to changing notation, we have that . We show that for any . By normality, we have this for . If we can write for . But then and thus Since all 3-cycles are conjugate to we have that all 3-cycles are in . It follows by Lemma 1 that .
- Case I
- contains a cycle of length .
The claim then follows by Lemma 2.
- Case II
- If contains an with two cycles of length 3.
The claim then follows by Case I.
- Case III
- If contains
We have that . The claim then follows by Lemma 1.
- Case IV
- If every element of is a product of disjoint 2-cycles.
We have that But then . The claim then follows by Case 1.
[Note: This last case is the only place where we really use this mystical fifth element. Without it, this last step wouldn't go through.]
Throwback to
- Claim
- contains no normal such that .
has an element of order three, therefore does. We then conjugate to get all the three cycles. Then is too big.
[ Suppose that , then
Which implies that , but since we have , a contradiction.]
Group Actions
- A group acting on a set
A left (resp. right) group action of on is a binary map denotes by satisfying:
- (resp. )
- (resp )
- [The above implies and .]
Examples of group actions
- acting on itself by conjugation (a right action).
- Let be the set of bijections from to , with group structure given by composition. We then have an -action of given
["Where does the shirt come into the business?!" Dror's remark after talking about the symmetry of a student's shirt.]
- If is a group where is the underlying set of and is the group multiplication. We have an action: this gives a map .
- is the group of orientation preserving symmetries of the -dimensional sphere. We have that as the subgroup of rotations that fix the north and south pole. There is a map given by looking at the image of the north pole.
- If which may not be normal, then we have an action of on given by .
- We have and .
- Exercise
- Show that acting on and are isomorphic -sets.
[Dror violently resists rigorously defining a category. Gives a little speech about "things" and "arrows". Gives an example of taking a topological space and then looking at the space of paths with identities given by staying still, and composition of paths given by concatenation.]
- Claim
- Left -sets form a category.
The objects of the category are actions . The morphisms, if we have and are -sets, a morphism of -sets is a function such that .
- Isomorphism of -sets
- An isomorphism of -sets is a morphism which is bijective.
- Silly fact
- If and are -sets then so is , the disjoint union of the two.
the next statement combines the silly observation above, with the construction of an action of on .
- Claim
- Any -set is a disjoint unions of the "transitive -sets". And If is a transitive -set, then for some .